Being pluralistic about philosophical pessimism (Part 1)
17 March 2025
There are many vernacular senses of pessimism. Familiar images of half-empty glasses go with elaborate talk of ours as ‘the worst possible world’. Pessimistic people might be praised as resolute truth-tellers or condemned as downbeat ‘doom-mongers’. Politicians often condemn pessimism as a call to apathy, a counsel of despair, or a spectacularly ill-timed valorisation of passivity in a world desperately in need of action. Champions of pessimism flag its corrective, balancing role and surprising status as a font of moral hope.
Others revile pessimism as un-American, un-Christian and an abandonment of Enlightenment values. Roger Scruton emphasises the ‘uses of pessimism’, while Raymond Tallis associates it with ‘poverty of spirit and meanness of mind’.
What should we make of these competing concepts and images? The term ‘pessimism’ suffers from being overused and underdefined. Is there an ‘essence’ of pessimism? Can we identify common features – and, if so, are they beliefs, arguments, or certain practical implications?
I think there is a ‘core’ to pessimism and that around it one can build different doctrines of pessimism. This means we should be pluralistic about philosophical pessimism. In practice, pessimists share a common core but vary on their characterisations of human life and their proposals for how to cope with it. If this is right, there can be no ‘knockdown’ arguments against pessimism: for there is no single target. We should assay its varieties, then assess them one by one, without prejudgment or pathologisation.
The conceptual core.
I think pessimism is a judgment on, or appraisal of, human life. It is sustained and modulated by experiences, thought, emotions and moods and habits of deliberation. It is not to be defined in terms of specific emotions, like despair since this prejudges which affective responses ‘go with’ various pessimistic judgments. Some pessimists despair, but others experience sadness, disquiet, or sombre resignation. It also connects, as a matter of possibility rather than necessity, to attitudes such as fatalism and cynicism. Certain definitions of pessimism build too much into it. Other definitions tend to prejudge the combinatorial possibilities, for instance, by regarding ‘hopeful pessimism’ as a contradiction in terms, despite the complexity of hope as a concept.
Pessimism is a judgment – or, better, two closely related judgments. First, the human condition, at least as we know it, is a bad one. More fully: it has one or more entrenched features necessarily destructive of, or antagonistic to, our efforts to achieve and to sustain deep human goods. While no serious pessimist thinks our condition is all bad, they all think it is significantly bad. Much work is needed to spell out these qualitative and quantitative claims: the slogan of some pessimists – ‘bad things are worse than good things are good’ – conceals messy psychological and axiological issues. The bad-making features can include pains, sadness, ‘absurdity’, stubborn habits of discontent, anomie and varieties of alienation, and the species of ‘suffering’ or ‘dis-ease’ encompassed by the Buddha’s talk of dukkha. Such features are not superficial, minor, or contingent: they are integral to the structures and dynamics of human life.
An emphasis on the badness of human life does not get one to pessimism, of course. All but the most delusionally ‘bright-siding’ optimists concede the pains, struggles, and sundry sorrows of human life.
A second judgment is needed: there is little to no serious prospect of the human condition being improved for the better, at least not by human agency. A pessimist thinks the badness of our condition is incapable of substantive, permanent improvement. Most allow a possibility of local, limited, and transient improvements in certain aspects of our condition. (Cioran thought the only clear improvement was in hygiene). Others recognise kinds of non-human moral agency at work in the world – divine grace, maybe, confirming the later Heidegger’s cryptic pronouncement that ‘only a god can save us’. Still, this is nothing we can bring about. The crucial point is that the pessimist must endorse these two judgments: our condition is – and as far as we are able to tell – will remain a bad one.
In fact, certain pessimists want to add a third judgment: the anticipation of deterioration. For them, our condition is bad, will not improve, and in fact will worsen over time, as a result of, for instance, the increasing complexification of social life or the accumulation of increasingly catastrophic decisions and developments. Anticipations of deterioration can be justified by appeals to human nature, induction from our historical track record, or attempts to model possible futures. (Others, like the Buddha, appeal to their alleged psychical abilities). We are ‘f*cked’, argues one author, for the simple reason that we never learn, repeating the same mistakes, even as their consequences increase.
For two reasons, the anticipation of deterioration is not necessary to being a pessimist. First, to be a pessimist, it is enough to think that our condition is bad and likely to remain so. We need not add a further claim about it getting worse. The second strategic reason is that it is very difficult to justify confident claims about the future development of humankind. If a claim is unnecessary and contentious, then it is best to leave it out. It is enough to think our condition is bad and enduringly so. Eco-pessimists are often tempted by deteriorationism – expressed in talk of ‘missed targets’, ‘tipping points’, and spiralling ‘polycrises’. But pessimism can take more than enough force from our current state. I elaborate on this point in part two.
There is also the objection that anticipations of this kind are self-confirming. Other anticipations may be publicly denied by those who endorse them privately.
My suggestion that the core of pessimism are these twin judgments of enduring badness is, of course, too sparse, as it stands. More is needed to elevate pessimistic convictions into something substantive—into doctrines of pessimism.
Photo by ALEXANDRE DINAUT on Unsplash
Comments
- March 2025
- February 2025
- January 2025
- December 2024
- November 2024
- October 2024
- September 2024
- August 2024
- July 2024
- June 2024
- May 2024
- April 2024
- March 2024
- February 2024
- January 2024
- December 2023
- November 2023
- October 2023
- September 2023
- August 2023
- July 2023
- June 2023
- May 2023
- April 2023
- March 2023
- February 2023
- January 2023
- December 2022
- November 2022
- October 2022
- September 2022
- August 2022
- July 2022
- June 2022
- May 2022
- April 2022
- March 2022
- February 2022
- January 2022
- December 2021
- November 2021
- October 2021
- September 2021
- August 2021
- July 2021
- June 2021
- May 2021
- April 2021
- March 2021
- February 2021
- January 2021
- December 2020
- November 2020
- October 2020
- September 2020
- August 2020
- July 2020
- June 2020
- May 2020
- April 2020
- March 2020
- February 2020
- January 2020
- December 2019
- November 2019
- October 2019
- September 2019
- August 2019
- July 2019
- June 2019
- May 2019
- April 2019
- March 2019
- February 2019
- January 2019
- December 2018
- November 2018
- October 2018
- September 2018
- August 2018
- July 2018
- June 2018
- May 2018
- April 2018
- March 2018
- February 2018
- January 2018
- December 2017
- November 2017
- October 2017
- September 2017
- August 2017
- July 2017
- June 2017
- May 2017